The obvious response to the preceding part (here) is that, while I am arguing that
Volume One of Capital can be read and
understood on its own, Harvey is arguing that capitalism cannot be understood
on the basis of Volume One alone. I suspect that that is indeed Harvey’s
position. I am not opposed to it. I admit in the Introduction to Marx’s Inferno
that “volumes two and three may deepen our understanding of how, according to
Marx, capitalism works” (p. 16). However, Harvey’s review of my book does not
differentiate between understanding Capital
and understanding capitalism. It simply proceeds as if the inability to
understand Fordism or consumer society on the basis of Volume One invalidates
my claim that Volume One can be read and understood on its own.
I am confident
that we have to read much that Marx never wrote in order to understand the
vagaries and varieties of twentieth century and contemporary capitalism. Nonetheless,
I also think that Marx, in Volume One of Capital,
does a better job than those who came before or after at getting at what is
wrong with capitalism (of whatever vintage). He is able to do so because (a) he
has a better grasp of the fundamental dynamics of the market, the workplace, the
pattern of capitalist development, and the role of the capitalist state than most
of his competitors, and (b) he shows how all of these offend against the all-too-human
desire for freedom from dominating power.
Contra Harvey, the
republican inclinations I detect in Capital
are not evidence that “Marx went far beyond [the utopian socialist] tradition
and reached back to an older tradition of republicanism.” The republican
concern for freedom from domination was all over the place in the socialisms of
Marx’s day. Marx married this concern for freedom to a systematic dissection of
capital. He shows how and why the market dominates the producers, the
capitalist and the factory dominate the wage-laborer, and capital comes to
dominate the state. Capital doesn’t
merely show us how capitalist production works; it shows us why we would, for
the sake of freedom, want to get out from under the regime of capitalist
production.
This argument prompts Harvey to claim that, while I have rightly drawn
attention “to the political in Marx,” I have gone too far in the direction of “dismissing
the economic.” I disagree. What I have tried to do, on the contrary, is to show
that Marx had a better understanding of economics than Proudhon, the Owenites,
or the St-Simonians, precisely because he saw what was political in the
economy, and in arguments about the economy.
Take Harvey’s claim, already encountered, that, in Volume One, Marx
assumed, contrary to his considered position, that commodities exchange at
their values. According to Harvey, Marx did so “in order to make the value
theory more palatable to his audience.” This badly misrepresents the political intention
and stakes of Marx’s argument. The default position among socialists in Marx’s
day was that the suffering and exploitation of workers was attributable to the
fact that their labor and their goods were unable to command their fair value
on the market. Marx’s insistence on treating prices as if they reflected value
would have made his value theory more controversial, not more palatable. Marx
was cutting against the grain here, picking a fight. Why? Because the
prevailing diagnosis, by harping on the divergence between price and value,
missed both the dynamics of the market (by which prices converge on value) and the
distinctiveness of capital, which can accumulate without extracting rents, as a
form of economic power. Far from soft-pedaling the complexities of his theory,
Marx is concerned to confront head-on the weak points of existing socialist
theory.
On the same theme, Harvey claims that, by assuming that all commodities
exchange at their values, Marx is able to “avoid” the problem of effective
demand, and thereby – “on the basis of these assumptions” – to construct “a
model of capitalist activity that reflects ‘the hell’ of the laborer.” But, as
I argue in Chapter 3, Marx does not “avoid” this problem at all in Volume One.
Rather than assuming away the issue, Marx builds it into his accounts of the
commodity, of exchange, and of money. (Ironically, Harvey himself points us to
two places in Volume One where Marx raises this issue; in neither place does he
say, “I will be treating this in Volume Two.”) That “the course of true love
never did run smooth” is one of the reasons that using the market to mediate
the social division of labor produces anxiety, uncertainty, and slavish
watchfulness among those dependent upon the market for their livelihoods.
If every commodity found effective demand awaiting it with open arms,
Proudhon’s scheme to “republicanize specie” would work (but would also be
unnecessary). If effective demand was assumed into existence by Marx, he could
not have produced his account of the production of relative surplus value,
since the ratchetting up of productivity could not operate unless more
productive firms could gain market share. Finally, if Harvey were right that
Marx assumes away the problem of effective demand in Volume One, and that he is
only thereby enabled to model capitalist production so as to reflect the hell
of the laborer, this would be a damning indictment of Marx’s book. It would
mean that Marx’s theory of exploitation, development, and accumulation rests on
a premise “simplified even to the point of falsification.”
I happily admit that my reading of Marx’s economic arguments in Volume
One is not the standard reading. Nonetheless, it is far from sui generis: it accords
with some of the theses advanced by value-form theorists, for one thing. These approaches
to Marx situates him as a proto-Austrian rather than a post-Ricardian (yes, I
know that will be a controversial claim!), and they transform the reading of
both Marx’s value theory and his account of exploitation. These are fundamental
economic matters. What my book brings
to the table is the additional claim that the political context and intent of
Marx’s argument is crucial for understanding the true content of Marx’s position.
When you appreciate Marx’s opposition to all the labor-money schemes, and you see
what was motivating those schemes to begin with, you are better positioned to
understand Marx’s arguments in Part I. When you recognize the contrast between
Marx’s approach to exploitation and all of the St-Simonian-inspired accounts of
exploitation-as-extortion, you are better able to appreciate the force of Marx’s
argument in Part III. That is my gamble, at least: Marx’s political context
animates his economic arguments.
In the final part of this reply, I will turn squarely to the relation
between Marx’s political context and our own.
[Addendum: I forgot to include a discussion of primitive accumulation!
Finally, there is the matter of primitive accumulation, which Harvey ties into the same issue of Marx’s simplifying assumptions. According to him, there is a “dramatic shift of assumptions” at the beginning of Part VIII, and “the figures of the usurer, the banker, the merchant, the landlord, the state (and its debt) flood back into the narrative, as does the power of effective demand in the market.” I agree that the landlords and the state are centrally important to Marx’s account of primitive accumulation, and say so in Chapter 6 of my book. Our real disagreement regards the importance of usurers, bankers, and merchants. According to Harvey, it is the autonomous spread of these “antediluvian” forms of capital that drives primitive accumulation: “the spread of commodification and monetization from Europe,” he tells us, “played a necessary even if not sufficient role in the rise of industrial capitalism in Britain,” for it “engendered the demand for wool that led to Britain being overrun by sheep farming.” “Land, labor and money were commodities way before industrial capital came upon the scene,” he continues. “The problem for Marx is to show how these pre-capitalist forms were transformed and adapted to work within the framework of industrial capital.”
[Addendum: I forgot to include a discussion of primitive accumulation!
Finally, there is the matter of primitive accumulation, which Harvey ties into the same issue of Marx’s simplifying assumptions. According to him, there is a “dramatic shift of assumptions” at the beginning of Part VIII, and “the figures of the usurer, the banker, the merchant, the landlord, the state (and its debt) flood back into the narrative, as does the power of effective demand in the market.” I agree that the landlords and the state are centrally important to Marx’s account of primitive accumulation, and say so in Chapter 6 of my book. Our real disagreement regards the importance of usurers, bankers, and merchants. According to Harvey, it is the autonomous spread of these “antediluvian” forms of capital that drives primitive accumulation: “the spread of commodification and monetization from Europe,” he tells us, “played a necessary even if not sufficient role in the rise of industrial capitalism in Britain,” for it “engendered the demand for wool that led to Britain being overrun by sheep farming.” “Land, labor and money were commodities way before industrial capital came upon the scene,” he continues. “The problem for Marx is to show how these pre-capitalist forms were transformed and adapted to work within the framework of industrial capital.”
There are at least two problems here. First, Harvey claims that, while
my reading of primitive accumulation “may be historically true,” it “is not
what Marx says.” However, Harvey does not – and cannot – point to anywhere in
Part VIII where Marx actually stresses the role of merchants or usurers. Harvey
points to the Manifesto, to Volume
Three, to the Grundrisse, and
complains that I “ignore all of these,” but he fails to show how Marx’s
argument in Part VIII depends upon or reproduces Marx’s claims in these other
places. In fact, there are only two places in Part VIII where the antediluvian forms
of capital play a role in Marx’s presentation, and in both cases it is a
distinctly secondary one. First, in Chapter 26, Marx says that the demand for
wool in Flanders motivated lords to clear their estates and turn them into
sheep pastures. This episode is integral to my own account, so I can’t see what
Harvey’s complaint is on this score. Second, in Chapter 31, Marx claims that “The
money capital formed by means of usury and commerce was prevented from turning
into industrial capital, in the country by the feudal constitution, in the
towns by the guild organisation. These fetters vanished with the dissolution of
feudal society, with the expropriation and partial eviction of the country
population.” In other words, primitive accumulation empowers money capital to
begin functioning as industrial capital. Money capital does not, by its own
action, dissolve the feudal constitution of society. Marx’s claim here is the very
opposite of Harvey’s. If we are talking about what Marx says in Volume One,
then I don’t see any justice in Harvey’s criticisms.
More importantly, I think Harvey’s reading of primitive accumulation
erases one of the most important aspects of Marx’s argument: the sharp, epochal
break between the feudal constitution and the capitalist mode of production. Harvey
seems to take me for a Brennerite, who thinks capitalism sprang up in the
British countryside and then spread around the globe. This is far from the
truth; settler colonialism and slavery and empire were essential to the
constitution of capitalism from the very beginning. I will say, though, that
what Brenner and his followers get right is that the capital relation that
structures production – the relation between wage-labor and capital – is irreducible
to either the antediluvian forms of capital or the directly coercive relations
of production experienced by serfs, peasants, and slaves. Only once the
capital-relation has seized on the production of basic commodities – in the
British context, it was corn – can “the spread of commodification and monetization”
really take hold. Commodification and monetization are not, according to Marx,
autonomous processes. They do not spread by contagion. A revolution in the
relations of production is necessary. Yes, Marx does claim that “the circulation
of commodities is the starting point of capital.” But, as I argue, he also
begins each major section of Volume One with a new origin story for capital: in
the circulation of commodities, in the exploitation of labor, in large-scale production,
and in the primitive accumulation of the factors of production. Harvey’s
reading, by stressing only the first origin, risks making the market into the
root cause of evil, and Marx into another socialist moralizer, inveighing
against money and commodities, merchants and usurers, cheating and gouging.]