Prior to Galileo and Newton’s experiments, gravity was thought to be a property of the objects affected by it, a property by which heavier objects accelerate more rapidly towards the center than lighter objects. After Newton, but prior to Einstein’s formulation of general relativity, gravitation was understood to be a force exerted by massive objects, operating at a distance on any other massive object. Since Einstein, gravitation is hypothesized to be a local perturbation in the space-time continuum, a distortion of space-time by mass. Objects in motion are not affected by gravitation directly; rather, the space-time though which they move is affected, and the curvature of space-time by mass registers with the observer as a pull upon the object, a curve in its trajectory.
An analogy can be drawn to the theory of social power. On one, very old account, the power held and exercised by a few is a property inherent in their souls, a self-mastery by which they are as stable and unmoving as the earth beneath our feet. The less powerful are both attracted to this stable center and liable to wander, like the planets, as a consequence of their own, internal variability and lack of moral weight. According to another theory – almost equally venerable – power is a force exercised by the mighty, which bends the less powerful to their will, securing obedience, consent, and even adoration. Power is a force of attraction, exercised by all to some extent, and affecting all equally. According to a third theory, however, power is neither a force nor a property of people, but a massive social fact, a curvature of social space. People act differently in proximity to power, not because they are forced to by the powerful, and not because they have weak souls, but because the path to what they want is bent by the presence of power.
Wednesday, February 20, 2019
Tuesday, August 7, 2018
On BDS and saying no to nice things
In June, I received a very generous -- and very flattering -- invitation:
"In the coming academic year we would like to organise in our department a mini-symposium to discuss new advances in Marx scholarship. We suggest that this mini-symposium includes three panellists: Gareth Stedman Jones, Shlomo Avineri and you. The symposium would also be an occasion to mark the opening of the Political Theory MA research programme in our department."
Academia is a peer-to-peer prestige business. We professors don't bring in the big bucks -- though many of us do very well -- and, generally speaking, no one outside the academy knows our names. What drives us, for the most part, is desire for respect and recognition from our fellow academics. Knowing this does not make me immune. So being asked to be one of three panellists, alongside very distinguished professors thirty and forty years senior to me is exciting, to say the least.
"In the coming academic year we would like to organise in our department a mini-symposium to discuss new advances in Marx scholarship. We suggest that this mini-symposium includes three panellists: Gareth Stedman Jones, Shlomo Avineri and you. The symposium would also be an occasion to mark the opening of the Political Theory MA research programme in our department."
Academia is a peer-to-peer prestige business. We professors don't bring in the big bucks -- though many of us do very well -- and, generally speaking, no one outside the academy knows our names. What drives us, for the most part, is desire for respect and recognition from our fellow academics. Knowing this does not make me immune. So being asked to be one of three panellists, alongside very distinguished professors thirty and forty years senior to me is exciting, to say the least.
The only problem? The invitation was extended by professors at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem.
I am a supporter of BDS, a campaign to boycott, divest from, and impose sanctions upon Israel (and businesses and institutions that cooperate with or profit from Israel's occupation of Palestinian lands). The goals of BDS are to compel Israel to: (1) end its occupation and colonization of Arab lands, (2) recognize the equal rights of Arab-Palestinian citizens of Israel, and (3) respect, protect, and promote the right of displaced Palestinians to return to land now controlled by Israel.
Whether BDS can achieve all of these goals is uncertain, but it is clear that the Israeli government sees the BDS movement as a real threat to its policy of entrenching and extending its conception of Israel as an ethno-state. The government of Benjamin Netanyahu -- the ego-ideal of the Trump administration -- has banned members of 20 organizations that support BDS from entering Israel. A South African model was barred entry because she was visiting Israel on "a program sponsored by the prominent South African Israel-boycott organizations SACC (South African Council of Churches) and SAJP (South African Jews for a Free Palestine)." Advocates for Palestinian causes and critics of Israeli policy are detained and questioned aggressively by Israeli security services when they travel to Israel -- even when they are Israeli themselves. Ariel Gold, the co-director of Code Pink, was denied entry to Israel -- where she meant to pursue a program in Jewish studies at Hebrew University of Jerusalem -- and had her student visa revoked because of her BDS advocacy. Israeli Public Security Minister Gilad Erdan proclaimed on Twitter that "Whoever acts for a boycott of Israel and comes here to cause damage, will not enter the country." Given these facts, I could not accept the invitation, no matter how exciting it was from a professional and intellectual point of view. My response follows:
Dear Professors,
Thank you for your invitation. I am honoured that you would wish to include me in a symposium on Marx’s writings, especially alongside such respected senior scholars as Professors Stedman Jones and Avineri.
Unfortunately, I cannot accept your invitation. This is not a decision I take lightly, but I am committed to honouring the call by our Palestinian colleagues not to engage in collaborative work with Israeli institutions implicated in the occupation. Taking this decision, I am mindful of Ariel Gold, an incoming student at Hebrew University of Jerusalem, who was refused entry to Israel just on Sunday, and whose student visa was revoked, because of her BDS advocacy. I am mindful of my own status as an immigrant scholar in Canada, and of the fact that it is easier for me to participate in academic exchange in Israel than it is for our Palestinian colleagues. And I am mindful that Marx was sent into exile, unable to live and write in his homeland because the authorities considered his words too dangerous. I cannot afford myself such a wonderful opportunity when similar opportunities for academic exchange and conversation are so unjustly denied to both the people of Palestine and Jewish and Israeli advocates of BDS.
I regret that we won’t have a chance to meet and discuss Marx in this context, but I cling to the hope that a new political situation will arise, and that we will get another chance to work together.
Sincerely, Will Roberts
I want to make my response public because I know that I am not alone in turning down invitations to Israeli universities. I also know that most people do not know how many such invitations are refused. We know about organized attempts to declare institutional support for BDS, but we do not realize how many individual academics are postponing the opportunity for academic exchange and intellectual conversation in the hope that a new and better political situation will arise. Without knowing how many of us are waiting and hoping, the waiting can only be longer and the hoping more desperate. So I make my decision public, and I encourage others to do the same.
Dear Professors,
Thank you for your invitation. I am honoured that you would wish to include me in a symposium on Marx’s writings, especially alongside such respected senior scholars as Professors Stedman Jones and Avineri.
Unfortunately, I cannot accept your invitation. This is not a decision I take lightly, but I am committed to honouring the call by our Palestinian colleagues not to engage in collaborative work with Israeli institutions implicated in the occupation. Taking this decision, I am mindful of Ariel Gold, an incoming student at Hebrew University of Jerusalem, who was refused entry to Israel just on Sunday, and whose student visa was revoked, because of her BDS advocacy. I am mindful of my own status as an immigrant scholar in Canada, and of the fact that it is easier for me to participate in academic exchange in Israel than it is for our Palestinian colleagues. And I am mindful that Marx was sent into exile, unable to live and write in his homeland because the authorities considered his words too dangerous. I cannot afford myself such a wonderful opportunity when similar opportunities for academic exchange and conversation are so unjustly denied to both the people of Palestine and Jewish and Israeli advocates of BDS.
I regret that we won’t have a chance to meet and discuss Marx in this context, but I cling to the hope that a new political situation will arise, and that we will get another chance to work together.
Sincerely, Will Roberts
I want to make my response public because I know that I am not alone in turning down invitations to Israeli universities. I also know that most people do not know how many such invitations are refused. We know about organized attempts to declare institutional support for BDS, but we do not realize how many individual academics are postponing the opportunity for academic exchange and intellectual conversation in the hope that a new and better political situation will arise. Without knowing how many of us are waiting and hoping, the waiting can only be longer and the hoping more desperate. So I make my decision public, and I encourage others to do the same.
Wednesday, September 27, 2017
#TakeAKnee and the Conditions of Peace
The national anthem at the beginning of NFL games means, arguably, that the fight on the field, and the partisanship in the stands, is bracketed within an allegiance to national unity, so LA and Denver don't take their rivalry too far, and don't forget that "We're all Americans." So when Kap sat during the anthem, he was saying, "nope, I'm not one of you -- Black folks in this country aren't 'Americans' and fellow citizens, because they don't enjoy the protection of the law." In other words, Kap was denying the performative myth of the anthem, that "we" are united as Americans. Black Americans are subjects, not citizens, and the American state is a conquering force, not a civitas. (This is why all the "unity" bullshit this last weekend is bullshit. "Unity" is just the national anthem again. Kap was denying that there is unity.)
Antifa make the same move, and signify something analogous: they deny that they are fellow citizens with fascists, capable of tolerating their abhorrent opinions so long as everyone agrees that the state is the arbiter of any disputes that get physical. Liberals like Jonathan Chait consistently think that the Antifa are claiming that "either the government or violent street fighters" have "the right to silence opponents of the left." But this is not the Antifa claim at all. They are claiming that they *are right* to fight white supremacists, not that they (much less the police!) *have a right* to fight white supremacists. They are denying that the state is a legitimate arbiter between opposed groups of citizens making incompatible claims. That doesn't mean they are claiming the mantle of legitimate arbiter, but that they do not think a legitimate arbiter is a possibility in this situation. In other words, like Kap, they are denying that the invocation of corporate unity is capacious enough to encompass them -- so long as it also encompasses people organizing themselves to make the US a white "ethno-state."
Both of these claims are genuinely upsetting if you think the constitutional and legal framework of the US is a legitimate one, one that imposes upon people the duty to work through its established institutions and legal mechanisms. But the claim to legitimacy is also -- and always has been -- a claim to have established the conditions of peace. Whether or not a polity has established the conditions of peace is not a moral question. It must, to some important extent, accept the people *as they are.* If people are not, in fact, pacified, you do not have the conditions of peace. You can argue that people ought to be pacified, but they are not under any sort of prior constraint to accept your argument, and you sure as hell cannot presuppose that they are bound to accept it before you have even offered it.
You want peace? You want people to stand for the anthem? You want people to acknowledge their citizenship in the same country, and under the same laws, as you? Fine. Then make the country and its laws fit for their acknowledgement. Make the law and its agents treat them as citizens. Give them a good reason to lay down their arms in the faith that no asshole who thinks they are less than human will be able to subject them to inhuman treatment. Otherwise, admit that they are a subject population, at war with your polity, and get on with it.
Friday, August 18, 2017
Antifa and Elephants
In the wake of
Charlottesville, the question of how best to respond to a growing and
emboldened fascist movement is pressing. People, by and large, take one of two
lines.
The Antifa line is: punch Nazis. That is, confront fascists whenever and
wherever possible, show them that their public presence will not be tolerated,
and try to make them scurry back to their holes to hide in the dark.
The
liberal line is: sunlight kills more Nazis than punches. That is, speak out and
hold demonstrations, if necessary, but don’t respond with violence, which will
only spread and encourage the fascists to become more radical and dangerous.
By
and large, people taking one line don’t have any patience for those taking the
other. Liberals think Antifa play into fascists’ hands, and escalate social
upheaval. Antifa think liberals give cover for fascists, and roll over in the
face of the growing threat.
I’m not going to take
sides on this question of tactics. Not because I don’t have an opinion (my
opinion: the Antifa are usually right about the present situation in the US),
but because I want instead to call attention to certain features of both
arguments, features that (a) are endemic to arguments about political tactics,
and that (b) make it very hard to even imagine settling those arguments in the
same time-scale in which they are made and are salient as motivational and
justificatory frameworks for action.
First of all, both
sides in this non-debate rely on a privileged stock of historical examples. The
Antifa think, especially, of the Battle of Cable Street, when rioting Londoners
stopped Mosley’s British Union of Fascists; the BUF never recovered. The
liberals think, especially, of Weimar Germany, where they see escalating street
battles between fascists and communists preparing the ground for Hitler’s rise.
These different
historical lodestones derive from different analyses of the social dynamics of
fascism. Liberals tend to see the fascist seizure of the state as a backlash
phenomenon: increasingly violent social struggle stokes the demand for “law and
order,” which the authoritarian far-Right is able to capitalize on. The thought
is that most people are basically apolitical, and just want to go about their
day-to-day lives. The more political disorder – of whatever sort – intrudes
upon that day-to-day, the more likely this mass of people is to become reactionary,
to demand that someone, anyone, put an end to the protests, the fighting, the
disruption. If this is right, then keeping the political temperature down, and
keeping the state’s monopoly of violence intact, seems like the safest path.
The Antifa, of course,
thinks this is not right. For the Antifa Left, the state is not a third
party mediating social conflicts; it is on the side of the dominant party in
those conflicts. If you expect the cops to handle the fascists, you’re going to
be disappointed to find out that too many of the cops are the fascists.
To be sure, there are
plenty of far-Left analyses that stress the danger of backlash. Gramsci, for instance, advised communist partisans not to mimic the fascists’
militia units lest the symmetry of the opposed civil warriors license the
state’s suppression of “all sides” – a suppression which would inevitably be
led by the military and police elements that also support or even comprise the
far-Right’s militia cadres. Precisely because the Left sees the state as on the
side of the dominant, it has always worried about provoking the “legitimate
monopolists” of violence. This is why the Left ought to always prefer (and
does, in fact, usually prefer) public, mass struggle to clandestine and
small-cell operations.
However, it is also
why the Antifa do sometimes embrace tactics that especially rile liberals.
Because Antifa expect the police to be on the side of the fascists, they are
especially wary of being identified. Hence, they are especially wary of being
filmed. Hence, they sometimes attack reporters covering protests. This seems to
have happened twice in Charlottesville, and it has Jake Tapper and Jonathan
Chait especially up in arms.
Fundamentally,
liberals don’t want private individuals making judgment calls about when
physical violence is appropriate. And they don’t want this because they think
such private judgments are both unaccountable and given to indefinite expansion.
I understand this liberal perspective. I don’t want unaccountable
people making decisions about the meting out of physical violence, either. But
I also think that liberals (a) overestimate how accountable the public authorities
are for the violence they mete out, and (b) underestimate the checks that Antifa
ideology and organization place on Antifa violence.
Leaving the policing of
violence to the authorities is not, in the world we actually live in, leaving
it in democratically accountable hands. And whatever tendency there might be
for political justifications of violence to expand their mandate, this tendency
runs up against certain counter-tendencies. It is easier to maintain the discipline,
fervor, and group-cohesion necessary for mounting effective street battles in the
face of actual, armed Nazis, but
much harder to do so with each step on Chait’s slippery slope of inference.
More importantly, for
me, is that the liberal opposition to Antifa tactics – like the justification
of Antifa tactics themselves – relies upon a predictive model of social and
political dynamics that operates on a timescale a thousand times larger than
that of the Twitter controversy cycle. To be frank, we cannot know whether the
Antifa opposition to the brown shirts of Charlottesville helps or hurts the
struggle against fascist resurgence in America.
At some point in the future,
perhaps we will be able to retrospectively ascertain this, but even this is
unlikely. Certainly liberals do not look at the Battle of Cable Street and say,
well, in that case Antifa tactics worked. Rather, they will explain the failure
of fascism in Britain by pointing to the stability and good order of the
British government, the elite consensus around the rule of law, or some such.
And the Antifa will certainly not grant that communist battles with Nazis in
Weimar Germany drove the electorate into the arms of the Right. Even if each
side granted the other its preferred historical case, there would be no basis
for generalizing the conclusion.
In the end, we all
want to act as if the deeds of a discrete set of addressable agents are
consequential and variable, even as we treat the actions and reactions of everyone else as predictable constants. Liberals
want to hold Antifa responsible for any reactionary backlash. Antifa want to
hold those who stand by and do nothing responsible for the belligerence of the
far Right. And we may not have the conceptual tools to do otherwise, to knit
together our ethical discourses of individual responsibility and our social
scientific discourses of large-scale movement and change.
The long-term and
large-scale dynamics of history are always the elephant in the room. If there
is no agreement about those, I don’t see how there could ever be any rational
argument about political tactics.
Friday, May 19, 2017
Why I am not a fan of “the radical Enlightenment”
Invocations of Enlightenment, Reason, and Universalism too
often substitute the name for the thing. Trumpeting Reason is too often a substitute
for offering reasoned arguments.
Take, for instance, the recent
claim by Harrison Fluss and Landon Frim that “core Enlightenment principles”
are “the original basis for modern political emancipation,” and that the
contemporary Left should “ground” its politics in these principles once again.
According to Fluss and Frim, the “Enlightenment worldview” comprises
five essential principles: rationalism, materialism, humanism, hedonism, and
perfectionism. I am immediately suspicious. Materialism and humanism are not
obviously harmonious, insofar as humanism so often relies upon an implicit spiritualism.
Why wouldn’t a rigorous materialism undermine any strict species distinction
between humans and non-human animals, for instance? (On this, see the work of
Hasana Sharp.) Perfectionism is just as
awkward a fit. Most versions of perfectionism rely upon a teleological
conception of human nature that runs afoul of both materialism about causality
and rationalism about the order of nature.
Are these doubts just a consequence of the rough-and-ready
form of a popular presentation? Maybe this “Enlightenment worldview” just needs
to be more fully fleshed out.
Perhaps, but I also have concerns rooted in what Fluss and
Frim actually say about the implications of these principles. They claim, for
instance, that “the overriding principle of rationalism implies that people
ought to have conscious control over the greater part of their lives, the
perfection of their talents, the ways they contribute to society, and how they
cooperate with others.”
No, it doesn’t. Rationalism is, according to Fluss and Frim,
the thesis “that the universe is essentially knowable and that all limits to
knowledge are merely provisional.” The knowability of the universe does not imply
that people ought to have conscious control over their lives. The universe
remains knowable whether or not its is actually known, and whether or not that
knowledge gives any individuals actual control over their lives. The rational
explicability of all phenomena does not even secure the possibility of
conscious control. Knowledge may just as well reveal the limits of our power as
extend that power.
Fluss and Frim also claim that “Since all people are
conditioned by common, natural laws, then there can be no stark separation
between different peoples, sexes, races, etc.” As mentioned above, this claim
can just as easily undermine the stark separation between different species,
and so does not guarantee humanism. But if it proves too much, it also proves
too little, since the common conditioning of all human beings by natural laws
does not in any way entail a set of common interests. We can affirm that all
human beings are equally human and then turn around and wage war on other human
beings over scarce resources or ideological disagreements. That “diverse needs,
desires, and conditions of flourishing are ultimately translatable across all
parochial boundaries” does not mean that our needs, desires, and conditions of
flourishing are compatible. I can understand you and still want to kill you.
As Fluss and Frim would have it, “it is only a movement
steeped in Radical Enlightenment principles that will develop ever more
coherent political demands.” I don’t think this is right, and I think my
arguments above show why. Adherence to abstract principles does not produce
political demands. Politics is not derived from principles. Principles are not
foundational, but guiding. If you are committed to rationalism, then you should
keep that commitment in mind as you make your arguments, not try to make your
arguments follow from your rationalism.
My inclination is to say that the Left needs more and better
arguments, not more rationalism. It needs more and better explanations, not
more materialism. It needs more and better organizational and institutional
ties, not more humanism.
Wednesday, April 5, 2017
Comments on Ngugi
I guess I am supposed to say something about Professor Ngugi's influence upon my field of political theory. I will speak prospectively, instead, about the influence I hope he has some day.
I.
In 1893, Friedrich
Engels addressed the Italian readership of the newly-translated Communist Manifesto. “The close of the
feudal Middle Ages,” he wrote, “and the opening of the modern capitalist era
are marked by a colossal figure: an Italian, Dante, both the last poet of the
Middle Ages and the first poet of modern times. Today, as in 1300, a new historical
era is approaching. Will Italy give us the new Dante, who will mark the hour of
the birth of this new, proletarian era?”
Engels had a
remarkable historical sense, but his guess was far off in this case. Dante,
possessing all the wealth of the imperial, Latin tradition, left behind that
language of popes and emperors and wealthy elites in order to write his
greatest works in the vernacular dialect of Tuscany, a region torn by civil
wars and invasions. In so doing, he helped to set the path taken by the European
renaissance, and helped to create Italian literature.
It is impossible
that an Italian could perform this role again, for the modern era has also been
the era of European colonialism and imperialism, which have subjugated the
peoples of the world. Italy was hardly one of the foremost colonial powers,
but, even so, there is no way that any author writing in any European language could
signal the postcolonial rebirth of the globe, the renaissance of the invaded
and colonized cultures of the global proletariat.
Engels did not
live long enough to see the beginnings of the postcolonial transformation. He did
not foresee that the watershed moment of cultural rebirth would be when authors
of the colonized peoples of Africa, Asia, and the Americas abandoned the
English, French, Spanish, and Portuguese of the conquerors and colonial
administrators in order to tell their stories again in the “vulgar” tongues of
the people. He did not foresee that the new Dante might write in Gĩkũyũ.
II.
The relationship
of language and conquest, language and domination, has been at the center of
Ngugi’s political theory and political practice. If Dante was primarily
concerned to insist upon and demonstrate the eloquence of the common tongue, Ngugi has been concerned to demonstrate
its power. The “civilizing” mission
of the colonial powers has always entailed spreading the masters’ word. To be
civilized is to be cultured, to be cultured is to be educated, and to be
educated is to learn to read and write and speak the language of civilization
and culture – the language of the powerful.
This resonates
here, in Québec. And “here” is also unceded Kanien’kehá:ka land, where it
resonates again.
An old article
from The Spectator can give us the
flavor of history. In the midst of curious incomprehension at the phenomenon of
Quebecois nationalism, the author notes that, while Montreal was (in 1963) 65%
francophone, “only 22% of its economic activity” was run by members of the
francophone majority. “Among the more uncouth of the members of the richer
race,” he continues, “an exceptionally offensive phrase is not infrequently
heard … when a French-speaker is brutally told to ‘talk white.’”
Bosses can no
longer issue this command to workers in Québec, thankfully. But this does not
mean that the compulsion to use the language of the powerful disappeared. When
the conquerors control the wealth, they don’t have to command explicitly the
use of their tongue. Speaking the language of the powerful just makes economic
sense, as they say. Thus, forty years after the Charter of the French Language,
pressure is mounting on Québec to improve and expand English-language
education, and de facto anglophone
workplaces are on the rise. The imperative is no longer a personal command. It
issues from “the way things are.”
Marx called this
sort of phenomenon “the fetishism of commodities.” In a society in which goods
and services move to the music of market-prices, our “social movement has for
[us] the form of a movement of things, and instead of us controlling this
movement, [we] are controlled by it.” We bow, of necessity, to the impersonal
power of prices. Is our labor-power worth more if we speak English? Then we
must speak English. No one has to tell us to do so. We don’t need a weatherman
to know which way the wind blows.
But the wind blows
bitter for the smaller communities of the world. Its howling drowns out the
small voices of history. The extinction of languages has, by most accounts,
accelerated to the point that 60-80% of the languages spoken in the world today
will likely not be spoken by any children within a century. The French fact in
Québec is not endangered to this extent. The language of the Mohawk people is
much more precarious.
There is an irony
of history here, though, and a lesson. Kanien’kehá was probably in a more
precarious position in the mid- to late-‘70s. Over the prior half-century, most
Mohawk families, impelled by their integration into the anglophone labor
market, had come to speak English at home. The passage of Bill 101 in 1977
posed an existential crisis for the language, since it introduced new
restrictions on instruction in languages other than French. The response among
the Mohawk community in Kahnawà:ke was to establish an immersion program for
young children.
In other words, it
took a political threat to the language to provoke a political effort to
safeguard and strengthen it. The open, avowed enemy is easy to recognize. Being
easily recognized, it is easily emblazoned on the banners of political
resistance. The economic threat is harder to counter, since it seems to operate
from nowhere and everywhere all at once. Because the domination of the market
is impersonal, it may not evoke the protest that a law or a command evokes.
III.
The project Ngugi
has called “decolonizing the mind” is not an idealist “revolution in the mind.”
Decolonizing the mind is a political and material project. It means
decolonizing the hand, decolonizing the tongue, decolonizing the classroom, and
– thereby – decolonizing the imagination. It means destroying the colonial and
collaborationist project of mastering the world by mastering the masters’
language.
Ngugi is best
known for his work decolonizing literature, orature, and theatre. But
decolonizing the mind is also a political practice of theory, and a practice of
political theory. Ngugi noted long ago that, while the anticolonial and
postcolonial intellectuals “were busy haranguing the ruling circles in a
language” – English – “which
automatically excluded the participation of the peasantry and the working
class,” “the most reactionary African politician, the one who believes in
selling Africa to Europe, is often a master of African languages,” and “the
European missionary believed too much in his mission of conquest not to
communicate it in the language most readily available to the people.”
This is still a
problem everywhere. The most sincere devotees of universal liberation couch
their arguments in language that is incomprehensible outside the seminar rooms
of elite universities, or address themselves – plaintively or legalistically –
to those who hold the levers of government. This is not an argument for “dumbing theory down,” or for forgetting that
“common sense” is often common nonsense. But Ngugi provokes me to wonder what
is gained by speaking the language of power, and what is lost.
Do we believe
enough in the mission of emancipation to communicate it in the language most readily
available to the people? As Ngugi insists, the alternative to sharing and
enriching the common tongue is abandoning it to the most reactionary forces.
Friday, March 17, 2017
Response to Harvey, part 3: Socialisms, then and now
The part of my book that Harvey most appreciates is my discussion of “Marx’s
relation to Proudhon, Fourier, Saint-Simon and Robert Owen.” Harvey is
convinced by my argument against G.A. Cohen, who (along with many others)
stressed the continuity between this socialist tradition, with its emphasis on “equality
and social justice.” My challenge to Cohen insists that Marx was decisively
opposed to much of this tradition, which he regarded as moralistic and mistaken
about the operations of the capitalist economy. Although Harvey is appreciative
of this aspect of my argument, I am left a bit puzzled by his response to it,
for three reasons.
First, Harvey seems to skip right over the point of my argument. In his
words, I argue that Marx “reached back into an older aristocratic tradition of
republican governance as non-domination,” which “transformed by the experience
of capitalist industrialism, produced a unique Marxist political vision.”
Harvey asks, “If inequality and social justice are insufficient to the task of
defining a socialist alternative then what might replace it?” He then goes on
to talk about Owen and Saint-Simon on industrial administration, without even
pausing to consider the answer my book proposes (and that I think Marx
proposed): freedom. The “older
aristocratic tradition of republican governance” was not just older and not
just aristocratic. The republican concern with freedom from servitude and
domination ran through much of the radical, popular, and plebian politics of
the nineteenth century. It ran alongside the Rousseauvian concern with popular
sovereignty and the utilitarian concern with rational administration, even as
it clashed with these. It preached resistance to concentrations of power, and cooperative
and deliberative association. My book argues that Marx’s entire argument in Capital is oriented by this republican desire
for freedom from domination. And so I find it disconcerting that Harvey only
mentions freedom once in his entire review, and then only to ask why I don’t
talk more about the Jacobin tradition of republicanism, “which is very
different.” I will return to the Jacobins below. For now, let me just indicate
that my reconstruction of Marx’s republicanism resonates with some analyses on
the contemporary Left. Alex Gourevitch has argued – in Jacobin and elsewhere –
both for the historical credentials and the contemporary salience of “a vision of a society of equal freedom.” Keeanga-Yamahtta Taylor has made a powerful argument for reviving the movement for Black liberation. Corey Robin has, for
several years now, called on the American Left to re-appropriate the politics of freedom from the Right. On my reading, Marx would agree with these calls.
Given that this is the orientation of my book, I am, therefore, also
puzzled by Harvey’s apparent attempt to rehabilitate the Saint-Simonians. Harvey
rightly claims that “Marx was reluctant to let go of the obvious enhancements
in labor productivity achieved under industrial capitalism.” He also rightly
notes that this reluctance was part of the basis for Marx’s appreciation of
Robert Owen. However, he then uses one of Engels’s footnotes in Volume Three to
bring in Saint-Simon, whom he reads as a harbinger of the joint-stock company,
which has the potential – “when democratized to include the ouvriers as well” – to provide “modes of
collective governance and administration” for the socialist future. I am
extremely skeptical that there is anything of value for the Left in the thought
of Saint-Simon. And, Engels’s footnote notwithstanding, there is no credible
evidence that Marx thought much of Saint-Simon’s schemes either. Engels always
had a soft spot for Saint-Simon, as I point out in my book, but Marx left no
record of sharing his friend’s high estimation. That Engels assures us, after
Marx’s death, that his friend had come around to Engels’s opinion is not very
credible evidence that Marx was “attracted” to Saint-Simon’s “mode of thought.”
For one thing, Saint-Simon was an authoritarian rationalist who dreamed only of
benevolent hierarchy and orderly improvement. Therefore, he was utterly allergic
to anything so disorderly as popular political movements or majoritarian
democracy or government from below. When Harvey seemingly identifies the
question of the socialist alternative with the question of how “to devise a
form of governance that will be consistent with the objective of the principle
of association [and] with the need to organize the macro-economy in productive
and constructive ways,” he frames the issue is a way that is very congenial to
Saint-Simon. I don’t see how it is congenial to a project of building a
political movement for universal emancipation, though.
Finally, there is the matter of the Jacobins. Harvey notes that my book “ignores
the Jacobin element” in the socialism of Marx’s day. This is basically right.
(The only caveat I will offer is that the British Jacobinism of Bronterre O’Brien
does appear in my story, if rather on the margins.) It is certainly right that
Auguste Blanqui and his followers play no role in my account of the argument of
Capital. On the one hand, Blanqui
produced almost nothing by way of theory, and what he did produce was not very
distinctive. Marx was concerned to close down Proudhonism and Saint-Simoneanism
within the socialist movement, since these were the two substantial bodies of
theory. Second, Blanquism was not a force to be reckoned with in the International
Working Men’s Association, which – I argue in the book – is the most relevant
context for situating Capital. There
was a migration of Blanquists into the IWMA after the Commune, but Marx hated
their conspiratorial methods and worked with his allies to shut them out. Third,
Marx’s relation to Blanquism has been exhaustively and authoritatively treated
in Richard N. Hunt's The Political Ideas
of Marx and Engels (an underappreciated and hard-to-find classic,
unfortunately); I saw no value in retreading that ground. Most importantly,
however, the French republican tradition, of which Blanqui is one offshoot, is,
as Harvey realizes, “very different” from the republican tradition that I think
influenced Marx. Rousseau had a massive influence on the French tradition, but
almost none on Marx (as David Leopold has shown). I simply see no signs of
Jacobin or Blanquist influence in Capital,
and Harvey does not point to any, either. If anyone else does, I would, of
course, be happy to revisit the question. But, in the absence of any such
indication, I am a bit baffled by the suggestion that I cannot pursue the
evidence that is in the text “without
first opening up the question of Jacobin republicanism.”
And so, to conclude, we seem to have come full circle. Harvey’s
overwhelming objection to my book is that it is a reading of Volume One. He
does not think that I can establish my interpretation of Volume One on the
basis of Volume One. And he argues against my interpretation, but not, for the
most part, on the basis of Volume One. This result suggests to me that I am onto
something. As I write in the introduction to Marx’s Inferno,
Marx undoubtedly thought of Capital as his chef d’oeuvre. Throughout the twentieth century it was relatively neglected, for it was supposed to be the seat of the Marx we already knew from the proclamations of the Marxist parties. Hence, people who were attracted to Marx but repelled by the parties went looking for one “unknown Marx” or another, as new manuscripts became available. This process has certainly enriched our knowledge of Marx’s thought, but it has also produced the rather perverse situation in which Marx is better known for his unpublished jottings than for his major public intervention. Ironically, we never actually knew the Marx of Capital very well. It is a long and difficult book, lacking the programmatic clarity and generality of Engels’s late works. … Volume one of Capital—Marx’s only fully elaborated and published work of theory—ended up being largely neglected. And, so, I think it is important to go back to it, to read it carefully from beginning to end, and to do so without presuming that we know what we will find. (pp. 15-16)My hope is that my book might provoke exactly this sort of reading. If it does, then I am sure that people will encounter things that push against my interpretations, that suggest other interpretations, that open up onto other interlocutors. Until then, I am grateful to Professor Harvey for taking the time to read and respond to my book, but I remain unmoved by his objections.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)